inference-review | The cell is a
complex dynamic system in which macromolecules such as DNA and the
various proteins interact within a free energy flux provided by
nutrients. Its phenotypes can be represented by quasi-stable attractors
embedded in a multi-dimensional state space whose dimensions are defined
by the activities of the cell’s constituent proteins.1
This is the basis for the dynamical model of the cell.
The current molecular genetic or machine model of the cell, on the
other hand, is predicated on the work of Gregor Mendel and Charles
Darwin. Mendel framed the laws of inheritance on the basis of his
experimental work on pea plants. The first law states that inheritance
is a discrete and not a blending process: crossing purple and white
flowered varieties produces some offspring with white and some with
purple flowers, but generally not intermediately colored offspring.2 Mendel concluded that whatever was inherited had a material or particulate nature; it could be segregated.3
According to the machine cell model, those particles are genes or
sequences of nucleobases in the genomic DNA. They constitute Mendel’s
units of inheritance. Gene sequences are transcribed, via messenger RNA,
to proteins, which are folded linear strings of amino acids called
peptides. The interactions between proteins are responsible for
phenotypic traits. This assumption relies on two general principles
affirmed by Francis Crick in 1958, namely the sequence hypothesis and
the central dogma.4
The sequence hypothesis asserts that the sequence of bases in the
genomic DNA determines the sequence of amino acids in the peptide and
the three-dimensional structure of the folded peptide. The central
dogma states that the sequence hypothesis represents a flow of
information from DNA to the proteins and rules out a flow in reverse.
In 1961, the American biologist Christian Anfinsen demonstrated that
when the enzyme ribonuclease was denatured, it lost its activity, but
regained it on re-naturing. Anfinsen concluded from the kinetics of
re-naturation that the amino acid sequence of the peptide determined how
the peptide folded.5
He did not cite Crick’s 1958 paper or the sequence hypothesis, although
he had apparently read the first and confirmed the second.
The central dogma and the sequence hypothesis proved to be wonderful
heuristic tools with which to conduct bench work in molecular biology.
The machine model recognizes cells to be highly regulated entities;
genes are responsible for that regulation through gene regulatory
networks (GRNs).6 Gene sequences provide all the information needed to build and regulate the cell.
Both a naturalist and an experimentalist, Darwin observed that
breeding populations exhibit natural variations. Limited resources mean a
struggle for existence. Individuals become better and better adapted to
their environments. This process is responsible for both small adaptive
improvements and dramatic changes. Darwin insisted evolution was, in
both cases, gradual, and predicted that intermediate forms between
species should be found both in the fossil record and in existing
populations. Today, these ideas are part of the modern evolutionary
synthesis, a term coined by Julian Huxley in 1942.7 Like the central dogma, it has been subject to controversy, despite its early designation as the set of principles under which all of biology is conducted.8
The modern synthesis, we now understand, does not explain
trans-generational epigenetic inheritance, consciousness, and niche
construction.9
It is possible that the concept of the gene and the claim that
evolution depends on genetic diversity may both need to be modified or
replaced.
This essay is a step towards describing biology as a science founded
on the laws of physics. It is a step in the right direction.
0 comments:
Post a Comment